The (Science’s Proper Role in Morality) Party Don’t Start Til I Walk In!
Alternate title: a pretend essay on Sam Harris’s The Moral Landscape: How Science Can Determine Human Values (Free Press, 2010) . “Pretend” because if a student handed in something like this to me and called it an “essay,” I would probably send it back, but this is a blog, so ha ha ha.
(Alternate alternate title: tl;dr. Fair warning — this is about 2000 words long, twice the length of my usual blogs.)
Thanks to my friend YK for prompting this entry by asking me what I thought of Harris’s ideas of a moral landscape. Just to be clear, what I write here is not in any sense a reflection on or a direct response to what he believes (or doesn’t believe, as the case may be); my opinions, to the extent that they can be, are entirely my own.
I also apologize in advance that I’m working from memory; the book had to go back to the library almost immediately, and although I do enjoy blogging about this subject, I don’t enjoy it enough that I’m willing to spend my leisure time doing what I do for work (taking notes, copying quotes, etc.). So mea culpa.
The Moral Landscape is a dense book with a lot to unpack. Harris goes into many diverse issues that are interesting and relevant enough that I don’t want to call them tangents, which is often a perjorative designation, and it would be possible to make the case that his book has several theses. However, what seemed to me to be the throughline is this: there is a mind-independent universe, and everything important in it is either material or can be boiled down to states of or relationships between material things. The morality of an act is determined by its consequences (for Harris, the pertinent consequence is “well-being” or lack thereof), which are material. The proper domain of science is the material world. Therefore, we can compare the morality of acts or practices via science and scientific study.
For Harris, at least as outlined in this book, the most important consequence of this conclusion is that the position that one cannot comment on moral issues from a scientific standpoint is untenable, and for a scientist to hold it despite having strong moral opinions is unethical. He applies it theoretically to argue against moral relativism and practically to argue that one has the moral obligation to stop certain things affiliated with religion, specifically Christian influence on US legislation and the status of women in the devout Muslim community.
Before getting into why he hasn’t entirely convinced me that this is the case, let me give credit where credit is due. I deeply love that Sam Harris is putting forward a “new” atheism view wherein being a good person is both reasonable and supported by science. This is a refreshing change from what seems to me to be a recurrent theme in pop culture and literature that doing anything but acting in an utterly selfish manner is irrational and “unscientific.” (You all know what TV show I want to use as an example; let’s make a gentleman’s agreement that I won’t even mention it, okay?)
Unlike other writers on similar topics, Harris makes a coherent and cohesive argument, using precise language and demonstrating familiarity with both foundational works of philosophy and the works of those who disagree with him. He’s a fluid and talented writer with great prose style. And I also like that his proposed understanding of morality has a multiplicity of both right answers and wrong ones, avoiding the false dichotomies that sometimes seem to plague discussions of ethics and the (I believe) baseless criterion that a robust moral system must point to a single correct action in every situation.
In truth, I have relatively trivial objections to the middle of his argument — the part in which, having made his case for his premises and definitions, he goes on to develop his theories with the assumption of their acceptance by the reader. It’s the beginning (said premises and definitions) and the conclusions that trouble me.
If I had to boil down my reasons to a single point, I’d say it’s because he still hasn’t convinced me that there’s any good reason to consider that values ought to be determined through facts. He does make an extensive case for the idea, but unless one already accepts his definitions, it chases its tail in a question-begging game. Furthermore, his arguments often seem to be missing support for key concepts, especially when those concepts are intuitively appealing to people who already consider themselves to be on the “side” of science. For an example, let me take his Laplace’s-demon-esque proposition that because everything important is material or based on relationships between material things, science will one day be able to predict and explain everything that matters.
I’ll focus on one of his specific claims: that it will be possible to measure well-being directly as a state of brain. Now, I have no expertise in neuroscience. So for the sake of argument, let me take the most optimistic view: someday, it will be possible for neuroscientists to match every state of mind with a state of brain for every individual. (Note that Harris acknowledges that the strength of the evidence for this view rests mostly on its holder’s pre-existing philosophical assumptions about mind and brain.) Even if this is the case, can we then say that, knowing everything there is to know about a particular state of the brain, we know everything there is to know about its correspondent state of mind? The answer isn’t obvious; I might know every material fact there is to know about you, but can I ever know what it is like to be you? How do the emergent properties of the experience of consciousness relate to the physical properties of neurons?
Harris seems confident that this and other micro/macro problems that are some of the biggest unanswered questions in many fields of science and social science reflect difficulties in practice, not in principle, and I’d be happy to agree with him, but he provides no argument for why this should be so. Other works I’ve read written by practicing scientists take the opposite perspective — that while science will soon be able to reduce almost everything to systems of fundamental parts with basic properties that operate according to solvable natural laws, there is something inherent to complex emergent phenomena that resists this method of attack. Again, I would be happy to reconsider this view on the strength of more compelling arguments, but not on a single author’s unsupported assumption.
(This mention of practice vs. principle touches on another criticism I had of Harris, which is that he seems to apply criteria inconsistently depending on what he happens to be arguing*. He warns the reader not to reject his ideas when they can’t be applied in practice because he’s talking about what’s valid in principle — fair enough. But his arguments against religion and cultural relativism tend to focus on how they cash out in practice**. Similarly, he criticizes a fellow scholar for ignoring the self-reported religious motivations of captured terrorists, yet several chapters previous, he suggests that particular scientists whom he heard claim to speak on behalf of the reconciliation of religion and science couldn’t possibly believe what they were saying and were being coerced by the social domination of religion.)
Another key to Harris’s platform is the concept of well-being, which Harris defends on the grounds of its being the only reasonable basis for a system of morals. He invites sceptical readers to consider any other standard for morals and challenges them to find one that does not reduce somehow to a principle about human well-being.
While I’m not convinced that none exists, that’s beside the point; proving a negative is difficult. But I’m also not convinced that even if this is the case, this is good reason to construct an ethical stance around the concept of well-being. Being able to re-state one concept in terms of another doesn’t necessarily mean that the second concept should be taken as primary.
Here’s an example with which I do feel comfortable: numbers. How can one explain what the numeral “1” means without reference to some material example of one thing, whether that thing is an object in your hand, yourself, or ink on a page that indicates a single element in a set? At the end of the day, the concept of number (or the unit) is, at least for us humans, unable to be expressed in a way that isn’t somehow related to the material world. And yet one would have to make a much stronger case to argue that therefore the proper domain of theoretical mathematics is the material world.
(Yes, I know that this proposition about the proper domain of mathematics is counterintuitive but not necessarily wrong. I chose it purposely. Again, my point isn’t that Harris is necessarily wrong — although I disagree with him — it’s that his argument is invalid in the logical sense.)
Moreover, as part of his discussion of well-being as an empirical basis for ethical thought, Harris does something I found recurrent through the book: his argument against positions he considers to be obviously incorrect tends to be along the lines of, “Look at it. Come on!”
While it’s true that my knee-jerk intuitions against some of the philosophers and ideas he dismisses like this are strong, I’ve also read excellent arguments in favour of them that changed my mind. When Harris first brought them up, I was excited to see what I hoped would be his equally strong counter-arguments. I was disappointed to find that there generally were none.
For instance, Harris criticizes feminist philosophers of science like Sandra Harding for suggesting that science as it exists is intrinsically sexist and racist, and he takes to task cultural relativists like an unnamed conference speaker who took the position that one can’t say unilaterally that a society that plucks out the eyes of every third child is “wrong.” I can see that there are interesting, compelling arguments to be made against these ideas. But Harris doesn’t make them. He relies on that knee-jerk feeling of “Come on!” without even making the explicit argument, “You know, these theories go against our intuition, which is an important part of moral reasoning.”
Finally, despite Harris’s calls for a morality based on reason and evidence, his conclusions, in which he condemns particular social and religious practices gets no more support than another, “Come on!” Isn’t it obvious, he writes, that women who live in devout Muslim societies have less well-being than women who live in free Western societies?”
Well, yes, it is — to my intuition. But I thought the whole object of choosing well-being as the core concept of a moral system was that it’s supposed to be empirically verifiable through measurable states of brain and body: it can be examined with the methods of science. And isn’t that one of the things for which the scientific method is (rightly) praised? Its ability to overturn our intuitions and correct our all-too-human biases? So if Harris wants me to believe on the terms of his own system of empirically based ethics that his moral judgment is correct and that the Islamic treatment of women (or the hypothetical society that gouges out the eye of every third child, or… etc.) is wrong, I’m going to need some evidence before I form my conclusions.
Well, everyone, I have plenty more to say on Harris, but this has gone on long enough. (I even cut about 300 words on details of definitions of health. You’re welcome.) If you’re at all interested in these issues, I hope you read this book, and that of Richard Dawkins, and Stephen Jay Gould, and David Hume, and C. S. Lewis, and Francis Collins, and… etc. And I hope we’ll have fruitful and exciting discussions in the future. But most of all, I hope we can all agree on the really important thing: my title is way better than any of theirs.
* Just like everyone else, ever, but still. If one rightly objects when one’s opponent uses this tactic, one can’t disregard using it oneself.
** Also, to be fair, this particular inconsistency makes a whole lot of sense, if, like me, you’re sceptical that one can wholly distinguish between principle and practice. But Harris does not seem to take this view.
I agree.
I think his argument is incomplete (I actually found much after the first two chapters to be borderline incoherent). I’m actually coming down harder on him than you are :)
I think the real core of his argument, at least the part I found compelling, was the idea that ethics can, nay should be tied to reality. In other words, “die moral relativists, die”. It is not openly arbitrary. I think the main reason I enjoyed the book is because he is one of the first people to attempt to radically rework our conception of morality to align it with a burgeoning neuroscience. If one day (and this day may never come) we turn psychology into a branch of computationalism, this realist/non-transcendent concept of morality is gonna come in handy.
Think of it this way: how do two people who are talking about morality but ascribing different properties to it, know that they are even referring to the same thing? Why do we use a common word “morality”? Is this not like talking about apples and parrots? If we start using the same word to refer to both, and people say: “no, apple is a red/green fruit that grows on a tree”, and someone else says “no, apple is a squaking bird of many colors”, they are not talking about the same thing.
But implicit in the argument on morality is that we are talking about the same thing, just ascribing different properties to it (the ball is red; no the ball is blue). So there must be some property that is inherent to all definitions, and identifies the common theme. I think well-being is the common property (you’ll realize this when you unpack just what the word “should” means). Just as “no pain, no death” is the common definition of health, though people disagree on how to bring this about.
Cheerio, and thanks for reading this; I hope you got something out of it more than just placating my desire for an argument :)
Nah, thank YOU for reading and commenting, YK, and also for making sure my thinking muscles get some exercise outside my very narrow, very introspective work :P
(Sidenote: I had issues with Harris’s arguments that assume health (and, analogically, well-being) having clear, intuitive definitions that are correct, but I recognize that this is because I happen to have a sister and some colleagues who are way better educated than I am in the field of health policy. I am relatively ignorant in these areas and can only point and say, “Look! They know tons more about this than I do, and they’ve made good arguments to me that concepts such as health and life are way more complex than Harris presents!”)
I did come away from this book feeling that morality must be tied to reality in some way, but not because Harris argued it well; it’s because, for me, I take it as a premise, not a conclusion, that this is one of the criteria that a reasonable system of ethics must meet. *How* it should be tied to reality, and why — that’s something I don’t know, not yet, and I felt Harris did a poor job of arguing for his answers.
It’s funny, because re: moral relativism, I’m happy to be on board with Harris’s most fundamental claim, that, as you put it, morality isn’t “openly arbitrary”. But I’m not yet happy to maintain that I’m on board with it for any reason other than my intuitive understanding of what morality should be, and I’m not happy to characterize most moral relativists as making this simplistic kind of claim.
(Maybe that’s why some of Harris’s arguments didn’t do it for me — because he assumed that’s how I’d understand the work of the moral relativists he was using as examples, but to my eyes, they’re trying to make more sophisticated points. Like, I have no idea what the every-third-child-blind woman he mentions was actually getting at when that anecdote is taken out of the context of the whole conversation. Did she argue that therefore no one should interfere in that society? Was she arguing that there are indeed such things as good and evil but each of us as an individual has no way of knowing if our intuition on the subject is more correct than our neighbours?
Was she arguing that the imaginary society was wrong but the political implications of saying it was wrong were also wrong? Tell me, Harris!)
Anyway, I think reading academic theory has numbed me to borderline incoherence :P Or perhaps exposure to my own writing is the culprit ;)
That’s the thing though, I can’t say I agree with the ‘intuition’ claim either. It is ‘well-being’, I’m prepared to stake my cards behind that. Cause intuition is one of those vague, relative, things too, and it is impossible to rationally argue against so long as it remains in the realm of intuition, and not subjected to reason. I’m arguing that there CAN be a calculus of morality, it’s just ‘in the offing’.
I don’t necessarily think he over-simplified relativists, but he definitely glossed-over their justifications for their position, and even slightly misrepresented them, as you say. Didn’t you feel as though by the time he got to Chapter “Belief” he really lost the point of his whole argument? OK, so neurologically moral beliefs are processed similarly to factual knowledge … so?
I think the reason I liked the book was because, as a proponent of A.I., even strong A.I., to me the mind has to get out of the vagaries of philosophy, and into hard computationalism. So I appreciate trying to get morality out of the mushy realm of intuition, and into the realm of science. It’s a matter of personal preference, I suppose, not much more :)
Hmmm, I’m not sure I understand to what you refer by “the ‘intuition’ claim”. Could you please elaborate? :)
Yeah, I felt at points that his argument lacked focus/clear relevance — although I could see how the digressions *might* relate to his main point, so I was willing to go along for the ride (also because it seems to me that almost every non-academic non-fiction book I’ve read lately doesn’t make an argument but instead wanders around related topics — not that I wish to suggest that the converse is even remotely true! :P)
And I did think while I was reading it that the implied A. I. angle (in the relationship of neurological states to states of mind) on morality would probably interest you :)
OK, wordpress, apparently “:” “P” = :P . Whatever.
I think I meant if a person just says: “this feels wrong”, or “this feels right”, that doesn’t open itself up to any other discussion than: “well this feels right to me”. Feeling is insufficient. But perhaps this is not what you meant be intuition. Can you have a discussion about why you might have a certain intuition, and compare/justify certain intuitions or say that others are wrong and why? If not, it doesn’t open up too many options for discussion…
You can say well-being is what “feels good”, and that’s OK, but this shouldn’t be mixed, I think, with what “feels *right*”: i.e. chocolate feels good, but has no truth value (so it isn’t “correct”, the word ‘correct’ doesn’t even apply there). Maybe it’s a fine difference.